Substantive Kant's Concept of Reason – Book Report/Review Example

Download full paperFile format: .doc, available for editing

The paper “ Substantive Kant’ s Concept of Reason“ is a well-turned variant of book review on philosophy. The two major questions involved in Kant’ s key philosophy focuses on reason. The first one which is fundamental to his hypothetical philosophy is those pretensions pertaining reasons and cannot be proven which were conducted by previous philosophers like Descartes and Leibniz (Beavers 11). The second one which is fundamental to his practical philosophy is the role that is subservient and accorded to reason by the empiricists from Britain. They declared that reason cannot be the source of vigorous principles like conscience or a sense of ethics and hence reason is generally inactive (Beavers 11). It is apparent that the practical reason is basically the base of moral philosophy as argued by Kant.

It is not ore clear which role theoretical/hypothetical philosophy plays to reason according to Kant. According to Kant, metaphysics is completely not possible (Beavers 11). But while he tries to put effort into the firmness of the knowledge (empirical) that is gained through the latter, it materializes that reason is simply a cause of illusion and error.

This exhibit well with reference to the sections of the primary critiques which include Analytic, Aesthetic and Dialectic which are mostly examined. But if this happens to be true, the philosophical reasoning status would definitely stand in doubt (Beavers 20). Additionally, it is noted that only in rare cases does Kant discuss the reason. This makes it complicated to interpret the positive and general account of reason according to Kant. Theoretical ReasonThe First Critique of Pure Reason section suggests that only substantive knowledge can be obtained through understanding and sensibility (Adams 81).

This means that our concept formation and the capacity of sense experience collaborate to shape empirical opinion. The transcendental dialectic that is the other section and which is large destroys the pretension of reason to present knowledge of an inspiring world that is beyond what is exposed by the senses. Kant says that “ Dialect is a logic of illusion” (81), that means a dialectical notion, is false or it is empty. Nonetheless, the Critique of Pure Reason is not supposed to be interpreted as a cognitive role of reason demolisher (Adams 81). Certainly, Kant wanted to restrict the reason’ s bound, though this is not similar to argue that it does not have a position in our knowledge.

Here, three points are essential. One is the relation empirical truth of reason, second is the task of the scientific inquest and thirdly is the optimistic achievements which come from welcoming the limits of reason. Additionally, the philosophical reasoning of sound necessitates that reason achieves its own knowledge. This is an assignment that begun though is not finished in the primary Critique. The reason as Intermediary of Empirical TruthThe primary thing to monitor is that Kant clearly states that in all judgments reason is the intermediary of truth.

Sadly, he develops this idea and the matter has shockingly attracted slight consideration in the literature. Conversely, some essential facts are understandable from the text. We create our own judgment concerning the world without giving it a second shot of thought. A bigger section of Kant’ s philosophical hard work is committed to revealing that all these decisions rely on different categories such as effect and cause, which must command our sensory imitation.

It is only when a belief matches these situations does it meet the truth’ s formal conditions. However, not unless we are essentially perplexed about something, all of our beliefs meet this formal condition (Wilson 649). Uniformity in observations is usually enough to verify daily claims of knowledge. The knowledge of the scientific field desires law-like wholeness. For example, to cover all the heavenly motion of objects but not the movement of the sun in relation to earth alone. Kant summarizes his stand that “ the law of reason hunt for unity is essential because lacking it would have no reason, and without that, no logical use of the understanding, and missing that, there would be a scientific mark of experimental truth… ” Empirical Law and PerceptionAccording to Kant, anything which links to perception is real according to empirical laws.

But such fraud, as well as the protection against it has so much to declare to dualism and idealism (transcendental idealism) (Fern and Ez 123). Transcendental idealism refers to our current concern with the form of experience.

Here, a new division between the different kinds of idealism requires to be highlighted. One, we have the dogmatic idealist, and these are those who reject the reality of the matter (Fern and Ez 123). This is one who has to major this rejection on presumed contradictions of the notion that there exists such a thing as matter in any way. Second, we have the skeptical idealist, and this is one who does not believe the existence of matter and thinks that it cannot be verified to have been in existence.

While it is right to assume that the dogmatic idealist is wrong, also the skeptical idealist is also at fault and this supports the human reason (Fern and Ez 123). The only thing that he does is to keep on challenging our foundation for stressing that matter does exist. We suggest that we could major it on a perception that is immediate but he does criticize that to be insufficient. This challenge coerces us to be continually watching even in the minute advances of normal experience so as to ensure that we do not treat as a well earned possession a thing which we would have attained only illegally.

We can now clearly view the value this objection of a skeptical idealist offer to us. If at all we do treat the outer objects as things in themselves, our position is as terrible as the skeptical idealist claims, and certainly even worse. Because of this, we need to adopt the single option which is the thesis that the outer things are simply representations. From this, a question crops up: ‘ is dualism the single tenable position in the philosophy of mind? ’ and our response must be yes indeed, but just only when dualism is comprehended in the empirical sense. If we get to contrast the doctrine of souls as the physiological study of inner sense, with the body’ s doctrine as a physiology of the object of the outer sense, we will discover that while there is more empirical knowledge to be obtained from the two, they are remarkably unlike in what can be non-empirically learned via them.

In body’ s doctrine as a physiology of the object of the outer sense, there is a lot of a priori knowledge which is synthetic to be obtained from the sheer concept of an extended impassable being whereas in the doctrine of souls as the physiological study there is no contrastable knowledge from the perception of a thinking being (Fern and Ez 122).

The reason is that even though the two kinds of beings are appearances the body’ s doctrine as a physiology of the object of the outer sense has got something lasting or fixed that delivers the essential thing that all transitory states are states of.

This enhances it to provide a synthetic concept which is namely the concept of space and which is an appearance in the space. On contrary to that, time which is the only form of our inner perception does not include anything which is lasting. It only provides knowledge of the alteration of the state of no object which they are states of. Everything flows in the soul whereby nothing remains still apart from the ‘ I’ that is simple exclusively because its representation has no content and hence no qualitative complication (Fern and Ez 122).    

Work Cited

Adams, Jessie. "A Critique of Kant’s Postulates of Pure Practical Reason•." A Student Journal of the Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, (2009): 81. Print.

Beavers, Anthony F. "Kant and the problem of ethical metaphysics." Philosophy in the Contemporary World, 7. 2/3 (2010): 11--20. Print.

Corey W. Dyck. "The Divorce Of Reason And Experience: Kant's Paralogisms Of Pure Reason In Context." Journal of the History of Philosophy 47.2 (2009): 249-275. Print.

Fern, Iracheta and Francisco Ez. "Practical and Transcendental Freedom in the Critique of Pure Reason." Ideas y Valores, 61. 150 (2012): 91--125. Print.

Haldane, R. B.. "Kant's Critique Of Pure Reason." Nature 26.656 (2009): 76-78. Print.

Ostaric, Lara. "Kant's Account Of Nature's Systematicity And The Unity Of Theoretical And Practical Reason." Inquiry 52.2 (2009): 155-178. Print.

Singleton, Jane. "The Revolutionary Kant: A Commentary on the Critique of Pure Reason--By

Graham Bird." Philosophical Investigations, 31. 3 (2008): 261--268. Print.

Sockel, H. "Investigation Of The Accuracy Of The Pneumatic Averaging Technique." Journal of

Wind Engineering and Industrial Aerodynamics 43.1-3 (2008): 1829-1839. Print.

Stine, William D. "Self-consciousness In Kant's?Critique Of Pure Reason?." Philosophical Studies 28.3 (2008): 189-197. Print.

Wilson, Eric Entrican. "Accessing Kant: A Relaxed Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason (review)." Journal of the History of Philosophy, 46. 4 (2008): 649--650. Print.

Download full paperFile format: .doc, available for editing
Contact Us